Ask Sawal

Discussion Forum
Notification Icon1
Write Answer Icon
Add Question Icon

W.C. Granstedt




Posted Questions



Wait...

Posted Answers



Answer


Kijiji App users can follow the guide given below to resolve the issues they are facing. Most of the apps might have temporary issues, which can be fixed at that time. Some of the issues for Kijiji App not working might be a network issue, load issue, login issue, and so on. For all these issues you can find ways to fix them in the upcoming sections.

Users can check the following solutions to resolve the issue. Kijiji App Not Working Issue might occur due to various reasons.

Users before using the app, check whether you are using the right login credentials or whether the account is banned.

Try the following steps to fix the Kijiji App issue.

Normally while using any app, we might face some issues. Mostly it will be a temporary issue that we can fix it and use the app further.

Now coming to the black screen/white screen issue you can fix the issue by following the guide below. When you open an app you might see a black screen and then the app might crash with or without notification.

Follow the steps to fix the issue.

If you face a load issue while opening the Kijiji App, then the server of the app might be down.

So try to open the app after some time.

Next case, you should check whether the wifi/ mob data is working properly.

In the last case, in case too many users are using the app at the same time, the load will increase. So try after some time.

Step 1: The server may be down so it may cause login/account issues.

Step 2: The wifi/ mob data is working properly.

Step 3: Check the login credentials.

Step 4: Check if your account is banned or deactivated.

Step 1: First, check the wifi/data connection

Step 2: Check the mobile storage space

Step 3: Check whether the app you're trying to install supports the android version

Sometimes we might not receive app notifications due to some issues. You can try out the following steps to fix the issue.

Step 1: First, open the Kijiji App>Notifications, then check whether the notification is enabled or not. In case it is not enabled, kindly enable it.

Step 2: If you don't receive alert sounds, crosscheck whether you have muted the app notification sounds.

Users who face Audio/video loading problems with Kijiji App can follow the below steps. There might be several issues but there is always a solution for it. Try this and enjoy using the app.

Step 1: First you need to check the mobile volume in case you have an audio issue. Use headphones and find out whether the issue is with the app or speakers.

Step 2: The video loading problem might cause due to poor internet connectivity.


Answer is posted for the following question.

Why kijiji is not working?

Answer


A century before Arendt, Friedrich Nietzsche described in his notebooks (published posthumously by his sister in The Will to Power) a choice between ‘active ‘ and ‘passive’ nihilism. One of his many aphorisms on nihilism was that it is the result of the highest values devaluing themselves. Values such as truth and justice can come to feel like they are not merely ideas, but that they have some supernatural power, particularly when we say: ‘The truth will set you free’ or ‘Justice will be served.’ When these values turn out not to have the power attributed to them, when truth turns out not to be liberating, when justice doesn’t ensue, we become disillusioned. Yet, rather than blame ourselves for putting too much faith in these values, we instead blame the values for not living up to our expectations.

According to Nietzsche, we can then become active nihilists and reject the values given to us by others in order to erect values of our own. Or we can become passive nihilists and continue to believe in traditional values, despite having doubts about the true value of those values. The active nihilist destroys in order to find or create something worth believing in. Only that which can survive destruction can make us stronger. Nietzsche and the group of 19th-century Russians who self-identified as nihilists shared this outlook. The passive nihilist however does not want to risk self-destruction, and so clings to the safety of traditional beliefs. Nietzsche argues that such self-protection is in reality an even more dangerous form of self-destruction. To believe just for the sake of believing in something can lead to a superficial existence, to the complacent acceptance of believing anything believed by others, because believing in something (even if it turns out to be nothing worth believing in) will be seen by the passive nihilist as preferable to taking the risk of not believing in anything, to taking the risk of staring into the abyss – a metaphor for nihilism that appears frequently in Nietzsche’s work.

Today, nihilism has become an increasingly popular way to describe a widespread attitude towards the current state of the world. Yet when the term is used in conversation, in newspaper editorials or in social media rants, it is rarely ever defined, as if everyone knows very well what nihilism means and shares the same definition of the concept. But as we have seen, nihilism can be both active and passive. If we want a better understanding of contemporary nihilism, we should identify how it has evolved in epistemology, ethics and metaphysics, and how it has found expression in different ways of life, such as in self-denial, death-denial and world-denial.

In epistemology (the theory of knowledge), nihilism is often seen as the denial that knowledge is possible, the stance that our most cherished beliefs have no bedrock. The argument for epistemological nihilism is based on the idea that knowledge requires something more than just a knower and a known. That something more is typically seen as what makes knowledge objective, as the ability to refer to something outside of one’s personal, subjective experience is what separates knowledge from mere opinion.

But for epistemological nihilism, there is no standard, no foundation, no ground upon which one can make knowledge claims, nothing to justify our belief that any particular claim is true. All appeals to objectivity seen from the perspective of epistemological nihilism are illusory. We create the impression of knowledge to hide the fact that there are no facts. For example, as Thomas Kuhn argued in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), we can certainly develop very complicated and very successful models for describing reality, which we can use to discover a wealth of new ‘facts’, but we can never prove that these correspond to reality itself – they could simply derive from our particular model of reality.

If something is claimed to be true based on past experience, then the problem of induction arises: just because something has happened does not entail that it must happen again. If something is claimed to be true based on scientific evidence, then there arises the problem of appealing to authority. In logic, such appeals are seen as committing a fallacy, as the claims of others, even the claims of experts, are not seen as grounds for truth. In other words, even experts can be biased and can make mistakes. Furthermore, as scientists make claims based on the work of previous scientists, then they too can be seen as making appeals to authority. This leads to another problem, the problem of infinite regress. Any claim to knowledge based on some foundation inevitably leads to questions about the foundation of that foundation, and then the foundation of that foundation, and so on, and so on, and so on.

In trivialising doubts about knowledge, the passive nihilist trivialises the pursuit of knowledge

At this point, it might seem that what I am here calling ‘epistemological nihilism’ is really no different than skepticism. For the skeptic likewise questions the foundations upon which knowledge claims are taken to rest, and doubts the possibility of knowledge ever finding any sure ground. Here it would be useful to return to Nietzsche’s distinction between active and passive nihilism. Whereas the active nihilist would be similar to the radical skeptic, the passive nihilist would not be. The passive nihilist is aware that skeptical questions can be raised about knowledge. But rather than doubt knowledge, the passive nihilist continues to believe in knowledge. Consequently, for the passive nihilist, knowledge exists, but it exists on the basis of faith.

Nihilism is therefore not only to be found in the person who rejects knowledge claims for lacking an indubitable foundation. Rather, a person who is aware of the doubts surrounding knowledge claims and who nevertheless continues to act as though those doubts don’t really matter is also a nihilist.

Scientific theories can be based on appeals to other theories, which are based on appeals to other theories, any one of which could be based on a mistake. But so long as scientific theories continue to produce results – especially results in the form of technological advances – then doubts about the ultimate truth of those theories can be seen as trivial. And in trivialising doubts about knowledge, the passive nihilist trivialises the pursuit of knowledge.

In other words, for the passive nihilist, knowledge doesn’t matter. Just think about how often words such as ‘knowledge’ or ‘certainty’ are used haphazardly in everyday life. Someone says that they know the train is coming, and either we don’t ask how they know or, if we do ask, we’re often met with the absolute foundation for knowledge in contemporary life: because their phone says so. The phone might turn out to be right, in which case the phone’s claim to authority is preserved. Or the phone might turn out to be wrong, in which case we are likely to blame not the phone but the train. Since the phone has become our primary guarantor of knowledge, to admit that the phone could be wrong is to risk having to admit that not only could our phone-based knowledge claims be baseless, but that all of our knowledge claims could be. After all, just like with the phone, we tend not to ask why we think we know what we think we know. In this way, passive nihilism becomes, not a radical ‘postmodern’ position, but rather a normal part of everyday life.

In moral philosophy, nihilism is seen as the denial that morality exists. As Donald A Crosby argues in The Specter of the Absurd (1988), moral nihilism can be seen as a consequence of epistemological nihilism. If there exist no grounds for making objective claims about knowledge and truth, then there exist no grounds for making objective claims about right and wrong. In other words, what we take to be morality is a matter of what is believed to be right – whether that belief is relative to each historical period, to each culture or to each individual – rather than a matter of what is right.

To claim that something is right has been done historically by basing these claims on a foundation such as God, or happiness, or reason. Because these foundations are seen as applying universally – as applying to all people, in all places, in all times – they are seen as necessary to make morality apply universally.

The 18th-century moral philosopher Immanuel Kant recognised the danger of grounding morality on God or on happiness as leading to moral skepticism. The belief in God can motivate people to act morally, but only as a means to the end of ending up in heaven rather than hell. The pursuit of happiness can motivate people to act morally, but we can’t be certain in advance what action will result in making people happy. So, in response, Kant argued for a reason-based morality instead. According to him, if a universal foundation is what morality needs, then we should simply make decisions in accordance with the logic of universalisability. By determining what we are trying to achieve in any action, and by turning that intention into a law that all rational beings must obey, we can use reason to determine if it is logically possible for the intended action to be universalised. Logic – rather than God or desire – can therefore tell us if any intended action is right (universalisable) or wrong (not universalisable).

There are, however, several problems with trying to base morality on reason. One such problem, as pointed out by Jacques Lacan in ‘Kant with Sade’ (1989), is that using universalisability as the criterion of right and wrong can let clever people (such as the Marquis de Sade) justify some seemingly horrific actions if they can manage to show that those actions can actually pass Kant’s logic test. Another problem, as pointed out by John Stuart Mill in Utilitarianism (1861), is that humans are rational, but rationality is not all that we have, and so following Kantian morality forces us to live like uncaring robots rather than like people.

Yet another problem, as pointed out by Nietzsche, is that reason might not be what Kant claimed it to be, as it is quite possible that reason is no firmer a foundation than is God or happiness. In On the Genealogy of Morals (1887), Nietzsche argued that reason is not something absolute and universal but rather something that has evolved over time into part of human life. In much the same way that mice in a lab experiment can be taught to be rational, so too have we learned to become rational thanks to centuries of moral, religious and political ‘experiments’ in training people to be rational. Reason should not be seen therefore as a firm foundation for morality since its own foundations can be called into question.

The passive nihilist would rather navigate using a faulty compass than risk feeling completely lost

Here again we can find an important distinction between how the active nihilist and the passive nihilist respond to such moral skepticism. The ability to doubt the legitimacy of any possible foundation for morality can lead the active nihilist to either redefine morality or to reject morality. In the first instance, actions can be judged using moral principles, but the active nihilist is the one who determines those principles. But what seems to be creative could in fact be derivative, as it is difficult to distinguish when we are thinking for ourselves as opposed to when we are thinking in accordance with how we were brought up.

So rather than such moral egoism, it is more likely that the active nihilism will simply reject morality altogether. Instead, actions are judged only in practical terms, such as what is more or less efficient towards achieving a desired end. Human actions are therefore seen as no different than the actions of an animal or a machine. If it seems like a mistake to say that an animal is evil for eating another animal when it is hungry, then the active nihilist will say it is likewise a mistake to say that humans are evil for stealing from another human when they are hungry.

Without morality, concepts such as theft, property or rights are seen as having only legal standing. Actions can be seen as criminal but not as immoral. An example of such active nihilism can be seen in the Ancient Greek sophist Thrasymachus. In Plato’s Republic, Thrasymachus argues that ‘justice’ is merely propaganda used by the strong to oppress the weak, by tricking them into accepting such oppression as what is just.

The passive nihilist, on the other hand, doesn’t reject traditional morality just because its legitimacy can be questioned. Instead, the passive nihilist rejects the idea that the legitimacy of morality really matters. The passive nihilist obeys morality, not for the sake of morality, but for the sake of obedience. To live in accordance with what is believed by others to be right and wrong, to be good and evil, is seen by the passive nihilist as preferable to having to live without any such moral standards to guide decision-making. Moral standards provide a compass, and the passive nihilist would rather navigate life using a faulty compass than risk going through life feeling completely lost.

Moral standards also provide the feeling of belonging to a community. Sharing norms and values is as important for sharing a way of life as is sharing a language. In rejecting morality, the active nihilist is therefore also rejecting community. But the passive nihilist is unwilling to risk feeling completely alone in the world. So, by rejecting moral legitimacy, the passive nihilist is embracing community. What matters to the passive nihilist then is not whether a moral claim is true, but whether a moral claim is popular.

This means that, for the passive nihilist, morality doesn’t matter. The passive nihilist values morality as a means to an end, not as an end in itself. Because the desire to belong and to be led outweighs the desire to have moral certainty, the passive nihilist cares only about the sense of direction and the sense of community that can come from accepting a moral system. The passive nihilist is like a spectator at a sporting event who roots for the home team just because that’s what everyone else is doing. The passive nihilist supports moral standards just because they are accepted by the community to which the passive nihilist wants to belong.

Just as epistemological nihilism can lead to moral nihilism, so moral nihilism can lead to political nihilism. Political nihilism is typically understood as the rejection of authority. This was the case with the aforementioned self-identified nihilists of 19th-century Russia, who ultimately succeeded in assassinating the tsar. However, this revolutionary form of political nihilism, which we can identify with active nihilism, does not capture the passive form of political nihilism.

The danger of active nihilism comes from its anarchic willingness to destroy society for the sake of freedom. The danger of passive nihilism comes from its conformist willingness to destroy freedom for the sake of society. As we have already seen, the passive nihilist instrumentalises knowledge and morality by treating both as important only insofar as they serve as means to the ends of comfort and security. The need to feel protected from the discomfort of doubt and from the insecurity of instability is what leads the passive nihilist to become ultimately more destructive than the active nihilist.

The danger here is that the moral and political systems that promote freedom and independence will be seen as less desirable to the passive nihilist than the moral and political systems that promote dogmatic acceptance of tradition and blind obedience to authority. Though we might say we want to be free and independent, such liberation can feel like a terrible burden. This was expressed for example by Søren Kierkegaard in The Concept of Anxiety (1844) when he described anxiety as the ‘dizziness of freedom’ that arises when we look down at what appears to us as the ‘abyss’ of endless possibility. Just think of how often being presented with a menu full of options leads restaurant-goers to ask the server for a recommendation. Or how Netflix went from promoting its vast library of movies for you to choose from to promoting its algorithm that would let you ‘chill’ while it makes choices for you.

Nihilism can be promoted by those in power who benefit from such crises

Nietzsche was worried by what he saw as the growing acceptance of selflessness, self-sacrifice and self-denial as moral ideals. He saw the acceptance of such self-negating ideals as evidence that passive nihilism was spreading like a disease through 19th-century Europe. In the 20th century, Erich Fromm in Escape from Freedom (1941) similarly worried about what he described as the ‘fear of freedom’ spreading across Europe. It was this worry that motivated the work of both critical theorists in Germany and of existentialists in France.

Arendt warned that we should be careful not to think of nihilism as merely a personal crisis of uncertainty. Rather, we must recognise that nihilism is a political crisis. Nihilism can be promoted by those in power who benefit from such crises. Hence even metaphysical nihilism can carry political weight. Accepting that the universe is meaningless can lead to viewing concerns about oppression, about war, about the environment as meaningless too. For this reason, it is not only politicians who can benefit from nihilism.


Answer is posted for the following question.

why nihilism is true?

Answer


During your enrollment at CUNY, a refund may be generated for you because of a scholarship, an excess of financial aid received , a loan, or due to an overpayment of your tuition and fees


Answer is posted for the following question.

Why did cuny give me money?

Answer


  1. Percent Volume distribution by Bytecoin Exchange on CoinMarketCap
  2. Buy Sell and Trade Bytecoin on Binance
  3. Bytecoin trading on OKEx
  4. Bytecoin buying and selling on Poloniex
  5. Trade Bytecoin on HitBTC

Answer is posted for the following question.

Where can i trade bytecoin?

Answer


  • function getTimeStamp() {
  • var now = new Date();
  • return ((now.getMonth() + 1) + '/' + (now.getDate()) + '/' + now.getFullYear() + " " + now.getHours() + ':'
  • + ((now.getMinutes() < 10) ? (" .
  • .getSeconds()) : (now.getSeconds())));
  • }

Answer is posted for the following question.

How to call jquery function?

Answer


When building more complex applications, you can use some tools.

You will build a modern web application with a separate REST API and a separate front end using the following technologies. You'll be able to take advantage of the latest advances in front-end development with the use of React and Django.

Instead of using a built-in templating engine, you'll use the React as yourUI library, taking advantage of its virtual Document Object Model approach and components that quickly render data changes.

The web application that you will use to create customer records can be used as a starting point for aCRM application. You will be able to create, read, update, and destroy records when you're done.

You will need the following to complete this.

In this step, we'll create a virtual environment and install the necessary dependencies for our app, including django-cors-headers.

Our app will use two separate development server. They will run on different ports and work in different ways.

We need to allow Cross-Origin Resource Sharing (CORS) to send requests from React to Django without the browser being able to block them because of this.

You can create a virtual environment using the venv Python 3 module.

The virtual environment can be activated using source.

Next, install the project's dependencies. These include.

The framework is installed.

You can create the Django project with the project dependencies installed.

We will use the following commands and utilities to build the project.

The project can be created with django- admin startproject. We have to name the project.

Let's use the tree command to look at the directory structure of our project.

Go to the djangoreactproject folder inside your project root and run the tree command.

You will see the following.

The root of the project is in the /djangoreactproject folder.

There are several important files in this folder.

Adding the packages we installed in the previous step will be the first step in working with the project.

You can open the file with your favorite editor.

The rest framework and corsheaders apps can be added to the bottom of the list by navigating to the INSTALLED_APPS setting.

Add the corsmiddleware package to the MIDDLEWARE wrapper.

The Python class that is processed each time your web application handles a request or response is contained in this setting.

You can enable it. The CORS_ORIGIN_ALLOW_ALL setting tells whether to enable or not the CORS for all domain.

In our case, since the React development server will be running at http://localhost:3000, we will add new settings CORS_ORIGIN_ALLOW_ALL = False and CORS_ORIGIN_WHITELIST('localhost:3000',) to our settings.py file. The settings can be added anywhere in the file.

There are more configuration options in the documentation.

When you're done, save the file and exit the editor.

There is a new application called customers in the /djangoreactproject directory.

The models and views will be contained in it. Models and views allow our applications to handle web requests and return required responses.

Add this app to the list of installed apps in your project's settings.py file so that it's included in the project. Open settings.py again.

The customers app should be added.

Next, migrate the database and start the local server. Changes you make to your models in your database can be migrated. Adding a field or removing a model are examples of the changes that can be made.

See How to create Django models for more information.

The database needs to be changed.

Start the local server.

The result should be the same.

The web application is running on the internet. If you go to this address in your browser, you will see the following page.

Leave the application running and open a new terminal to continue developing the project.

In this section, we are going to create the application for our project.

You can quickly build React projects with the official tool. Webpack is a module packager used to bundle web resources. You don't have to deal with Webpack directly until you decide you need more control thanks to the create-react-app tool. The create-react-app can be run with the npm package binaries.

Make sure you are in your project directory in your second terminal.

The create-react-app and npx are needed to create a frontend.

Go inside your app and start the server.

The app will run from the internet.

Leave the server running and open another window to proceed.

To see the directory structure of the entire project, you have to navigate to the root folder and run the tree command again.

You will see a structure like this.

The app will use bootstrap 4 to make the interface, so we'll include it in the app.css file.

You can open the file.

The beginning of the file should be added with the import. You don't have to remove the existing content.

The style rules from other style sheets are imported using the CSS statement.

Now that we've created the back-end and front-end applications, let's create the client model and some test data.

The next step is to create the client model, which will represent the database table that will store information about the clients. Since you don't need a database, you can use ORM to map Python classes and variables to the tables and columns. This is how the Django ORM extracts the data from the database.

Your virtual environment should be activated again.

You can open models.py in the customers directory.

The file will have some content.

The import from django.db is what brought the client modelAPI into the file.

The Customer class extends models.model. Each model is a Python class.

The database fields will be in the Customer model.


Answer is posted for the following question.

How to use reverse function in django?


Wait...